第 31 节
作者:巴乔的中场      更新:2021-02-19 19:22      字数:9322
  rectification and extension of our judgements of taste。 But that matter is not one of exhibiting the determining ground of aesthetic judgements of this kind in a universally applicable formula…which is impossible。 Rather is it the investigation of the faculties of cognition and their function in these judgements; and the illustration; by the analysis of examples; of their mutual subjective finality; the form of which in a given representation has been shown above to constitute the beauty of their object。 Hence with regard to the representation whereby an object is given; the critique of taste itself is only subjective; viz。; it is the art or science of reducing the mutual relation of the understanding and the imagination in the given representation (without reference to antecedent sensation or concept); consequently their accordance or discordance; to rules; and of determining them with regard to their conditions。 It is art if it only illustrates this by examples; it is science if it deduces the possibility of such an estimate from the nature of these faculties as faculties of knowledge…in general。 It is only with the latter; as transcendental critique; that we have here any concern。 Its proper scope is the development and justification of the subjective principle of taste; as an a priori principle of judgement。 As an art; critique merely looks to the physiological (here psychological) and; consequently; empirical rules; according to which in actual fact taste proceeds (passing by the question of their possibility) and seeks to apply them in estimating its objects。 The latter critique criticizes the products of fine art; just as the former does the faculty of estimating them。
  SS 35。 The principle of taste is the subjective principle                of the general power of judgement。
  The judgement of taste is differentiated from logical judgement by the fact that; whereas the latter subsumes a representation under a concept of the object; the judgement of taste does not subsume under a concept at all…for; if it did; necessary and universal approval would be capable of being enforced by proofs。 And yet it does bear this resemblance to the logical judgement; that it asserts a universality and necessity; not; however; according to concepts of the object; but a universality and necessity that are; consequently; merely subjective。 Now the concepts in a judgement constitute its content (what belongs to the cognition of the object)。 But the judgement of taste is not determinable by means of concepts。 Hence it can only have its ground in the subjective formal condition of a judgement in general。 The subjective condition of all judgements is the judging faculty itself; or judgement。 Employed in respect of a representation whereby an object is given; this requires the harmonious accordance of two powers of representation。 These are: the imagination (for the intuition and the arrangement of the manifold of intuition); and the understanding (for the concept as a representation of the unity of this arrangement)。 Now; since no concept of the object underlies the judgement here; it can consist only in the subsumption of the imagination itself (in the case of a representation whereby an object is given) under the conditions enabling the understanding in general to advance from the intuition to concepts。 That is to say; since the freedom of the imagination consists precisely in the fact that it schematizes without a concept; the judgement of taste must found upon a mere sensation of the mutually quickening activity of the imagination in its freedom; and of the understanding with its conformity to law。 It must therefore rest upon a feeling that allows the object to be estimated by the finality of the representation (by which an object is given) for the furtherance of the cognitive faculties in their free play。 Taste; then; as a subjective power of judgement; contains a principle of subsumption; not of intuitions under concepts; but of the faculty of intuitions or presentations; i。e。; of the imagination; under the faculty of concepts; i。e。; the understanding; so far as the former in its freedom accords with the latter in its conformity to law。   For the discovery of this title by means of a deduction of judgements of taste; we can only avail ourselves of the guidance of the formal peculiarities of judgements of this kind; and consequently the mere consideration of their logical form。
  SS 36。 The problem of a deduction of judgements of taste。
  To form a cognitive judgement we may immediately connect with the perception of an object the concept of an object in general; the empirical predicates of which are contained in that perception。 In this way; a judgement of experience is produced。 Now this judgement rests on the foundation of a priori concepts of the synthetical unity of the manifold of intuition; enabling it to be thought as the determination of an object。 These concepts (the categories) call for a deduction; and such was supplied in the Critique of Pure Reason。 That deduction enabled us to solve the problem: How are synthetical a priori cognitive judgements possible? This problem had; accordingly; to do with the a priori principles of pure understanding and its theoretical judgements。   But we may also immediately connect with a perception a feeling of pleasure (or displeasure) and a delight; attending the representation of the object and serving it instead of a predicate。 In this way there arises a judgement which is aesthetic and not cognitive。 Now; if such a judgement is not merely one of sensation; but a formal judgement of reflection that exacts this delight from everyone as necessary; something must lie at its basis as its a priori principle。 This principle may; indeed; be a mere subjective one (supposing an objective one should be impossible for judgements of this kind); but; even as such; it requires a deduction to make it intelligible how an aesthetic judgement can lay claim to necessity。 That; now; is what lies at the bottom of the problem upon which we are at present engaged; i。e。: How are judgements of taste possible? This problem; therefore; is concerned with the a priori principles of pure judgement in aesthetic judgements; i。e。; not those in which (as in theoretical judgements) it has merely to subsume under objective concepts of understanding; and in which it comes under a law; but rather those in which it is itself; subjectively; object as well as law。   We may also put the problem in this way: How a judgement possible which; going merely upon the individual's own feeling of pleasure in an object independent of the concept of it; estimates this as a pleasure attached to the representation of the same object in every other individual; and does so a priori; i。e。; without being allowed to wait and see if other people will be of the same mind?   It is easy to see that judgements of taste are synthetic; for they go beyond the concept and even the intuition of the object; and join as predicate to that intuition something which is not even a cognition at all; namely; the feeling of pleasure (or displeasure)。 But; although the predicate (the personal pleasure that is connected with the representation) is empirical; still we need not go further than what is involved in the expressions of their claim to see that; so far as concerns the agreement required of everyone; they are a priori judgements; or mean to pass for such。 This problem of the Critique of judgement; therefore; is part of the general problem of transcendental philosophy: How are synthetic a priori judgements possible?
  SS 37。 What exactly it is that is asserted a priori of an                  object in a judgement of taste。
  The immediate synthesis of the representation of an object with pleasure can only be a matter of internal perception; and; were nothing more than this sought to be indicated; would only yield a mere empirical judgement。 For with no representation can I a priori connect a determinate feeling (of pleasure or displeasure) except where I rely upon the basis of an a priori principle in reason determining the will。 The truth is that the pleasure (in the moral feeling) is the consequence of the determination of the will by the principle。 It cannot; therefore; be compared with the pleasure in taste。 For it requires a determinate concept of a law: whereas the pleasure in taste has to be connected immediately with the sample estimate prior to any concept。 For the same reason; also; all judgements of taste are singular judgements; for they unite their predicate of delight; not to a concept; but to a given singular empirical representation。   Hence; in a judgement of taste; what is represented a priori as a universal rule for the judgement and as valid for everyone; is not the pleasure but the universal validity of this pleasure perceived; as it is; to be combined in the mind with the mere estimate of an object。 A judgement to the effect that it is with pleasure that I perceive and estimate some object is an empirical judgement。 But if it asserts that I think the object beautiful; i。e。; that I may attribute that delight to everyone as necessary; it is then an a priori judgement。
  SS 38。 Deduction of judgements of taste。
  Adm