第 19 节
作者:寻找山吹      更新:2024-04-07 21:07      字数:9322
  other from the idea of public right。 They are: I。 The contract of
  donation (pactum donationis); II。 The contract of loan (commodatum);
  III。 The action of real revindication (vindicatio); and IV。
  Guarantee by oath (juramentum)。
  It is a common error on the part of the jurist to fall here into the
  fallacy of begging the question by a tacit assumption (vitium
  subreptionis)。 This is done by assuming as objective and absolute
  the juridical principle which a public court of justice is entitled
  and even bound to adopt in its own behoof; and only from the
  subjective purpose of qualifying itself to decide and judge upon all
  the rights pertaining to individuals。 It is therefore of no small
  importance to make this specific difference intelligible; and to
  draw attention to it。
  37。 I。 The Contract of Donation。
  (Pactum Donationis)。
  The contract of donation signifies the gratuitous alienation
  (gratis) of a thing or right that is mine。 It involves a relation
  between me as the donor (donans); and another person as the donatory
  (donatarius); in accordance with the principle of private right; by
  which what is mine is transferred to the latter; on his acceptance
  of it; as a gift (donum)。 However; it is not to be presumed that I
  have voluntarily bound myself thereby so as to be compelled to keep my
  promise; and that I have thus given away my freedom gratuitously; and;
  as it were; to that extent thrown myself away。 Nemo suum jactare
  praesumitur。 But this is what would happen; under such
  circumstances; according to the principle of right in the civil state;
  for in this sphere the donatory can compel me; under certain
  conditions; to perform my promise。 If; then; the case comes before a
  court; according to the conditions of public right; it must either
  be presumed that the donor has consented to such compulsion; or the
  court would give no regard; in the sentence; to the consideration as
  to whether he intended to reserve the right to resile from his promise
  or not; but would only refer to what is certain; namely; the condition
  of the promise and the acceptance of the donatory。 Although the
  promiser; therefore; thought… as may easily be supposed… that he could
  not be bound by his promise in any case; if he 〃rued〃 it before it was
  actually carried out; yet the court assumes that he ought expressly to
  have reserved this condition if such was his mind; and if he did not
  make such an express reservation; it will be held that he can be
  compelled to implement his promise。 And this principle is assumed by
  the court; because the administration of justice would otherwise be
  endlessly impeded; or even made entirely impossible。
  38。 II。 The Contract of Loan。 (Commodatum)。
  In the contract of commodate…loan (commodatum) I give some one the
  gratuitous use of something that is mine。 If it is a thing that is
  given on loan; the contracting parties agree that the borrower will
  restore the very same thing to the power of the lender; But the
  receiver of the loan (commodatarius) cannot; at the same time;
  assume that the owner of the thing lent (commodans) will take upon
  himself all risk (casus) of any possible loss of it; or of its
  useful quality; that may arise from having given it into the
  possession of the receiver。 For it is not to be understood of itself
  that the owner; besides the use of the thing; which he has granted
  to the receiver; and the detriment that is inseparable from such
  use; also gives a guarantee or warrandice against all damage that
  may arise from such use。 On the contrary; a special accessory contract
  would have to be entered into for this purpose。 The only question;
  then; that can be raised is this: 〃Is it incumbent on the lender or
  the borrower to add expressly the condition of undertaking the risk
  that may accrue to the thing lent; or; if this is not done; which of
  the parties is to be presumed to have consented and agreed to
  guarantee the property of the lender; up to restoration of the very
  same thing or its equivalent?〃 Certainly not the lender; because it
  cannot be presumed that he has gratuitously agreed to give more than
  the mere use of the thing; so that he cannot be supposed to have
  also undertaken the risk of loss of his property。 But this may be
  assumed on the side of the borrower; because he thereby undertakes and
  performs nothing more than what is implied in the contract。
  For example; I enter a house; when overtaken by a shower of rain;
  and ask the loan of a cloak。 But through accidental contact with
  colouring matter; it becomes entirely spoiled while in my
  possession; or on entering another house; I lay it aside and it is
  stolen。 Under such circumstances; everybody would think it absurd
  for me to assert that I had no further concern with the cloak but to
  return it as it was; or; in the latter case; only to mention the
  fact of the theft; and that; in any case; anything more required would
  be but an act of courtesy in expressing sympathy with the owner on
  account of his loss; seeing he can claim nothing on the ground of
  right。 It would be otherwise; however; if; on asking the use of an
  article; I discharged myself beforehand from all responsibility; in
  case of its coming to grief while in my hands; on the ground of my
  being poor and unable to compensate any incidental loss。 No one
  could find such a condition superfluous or ludicrous; unless the
  borrower were; in fact; known to be a well…to…do and well…disposed
  man; because in such a case it would almost be an insult not to act on
  the presumption of generous compensation for any loss sustained。
  Now by the very nature of this contract; the possible damage (casus)
  which the thing lent may undergo cannot be exactly determined in any
  agreement。 Commodate is therefore an uncertain contract (pactum
  incertum); because the consent can only be so far presumed。 The
  judgement; in any case; deciding upon whom the incidence of any loss
  must fall; cannot therefore be determined from the conditions of the
  contract in itself; but only by the principle of the court before
  which it comes; and which can only consider what is certain in the
  contract; and the only thing certain is always the fact as to the
  possession of the thing as property。 Hence the judgement passed in the
  state of nature will be different from that given by a court of
  justice in the civil state。 The judgement from the standpoint of
  natural right will be determined by regard to the inner rational
  quality of the thing; and will run thus: 〃Loss arising from damage
  accruing to a thing lent falls upon the borrower〃 (casum sentit
  commodatarius); whereas the sentence of a court of justice in the
  civil state will run thus: 〃The loss falls upon the lender〃 (casum
  sentit dominus)。 The latter judgement turns out differently from the
  former as the sentence of the mere sound reason; because a public
  judge cannot found upon presumptions as to what either party may
  have thought; and thus the one who has not obtained release from all
  loss in the thing; by a special accessory contract; must bear the
  loss。 Hence the difference between the judgement as the court must
  deliver it and the form in which each individual is entitled to hold
  it for himself; by his private reason; is a matter of importance;
  and is not to be overlooked in the consideration of juridical
  judgements。
  39。 III。 The Revindication of what has been Lost。
  (Vindicatio)。
  It is clear from what has been already said that a thing of mine
  which continues to exist remains mine; although I may not be in
  continuous occupation of it; and that it does not cease to be mine
  without a juridical act of dereliction or alienation。 Further; it is
  evident that a right in this thing (jus reale) belongs in
  consequence to me (jus personale); against every holder of it; and not
  merely against some particular person。 But the question now arises
  as to whether this right must be regarded by every other person as a
  continuous right of property per se; if I have not in any way
  renounced it; although the thing is in the possession of another。
  A thing may be lost (res amissa) and thus come into other hands in
  an honourable bona fide way as a supposed 〃find〃; or it may come to me
  by formal transfer on the part of one who is in possession of it;
  and who professes to be its owner; although he is not so。 Taking the
  latter case; the question arises whether; since I cannot acquire a
  thing from one who is not its owner (a non domino); I am excluded by
  the fact from all right in the thing itself; and have merely a
  personal right against a wrongful possessor? This is manifestly so; if
  the acquisition is judged purely according to its inner justifying
  grounds and viewed according to the state of nature; and not according
  to the convenience of a court of justice。
  For everything alienable must be capable of being acquired by